4. ENTERTAINED ARGUMENTS

In section 2 we looked at some of the basic structures of argument. In all the cases we have looked at, the person putting forward the argument has actually asserted the premises she has been using; she has been committed to the premises and to the conclusions they are intended to support. Now while we often are so committed, it is important to see that we can also argue in a different way: we merely suppose something, or we assume something for the sake of the argument, or, as philosophers sometimes say, we entertain a thought to see where it may lead.

The general pattern of such arguments involves the arguer in first supposing something and then asserting something else within the scope of the supposition. We can do this openly, as for instance, by saying "Let's suppose..." or "Let ABC be a triangle,...". But perhaps more commonly we begin to disguise what we are doing by using conditional sentences (sentences constructed out of "if...then...") which sometimes feel like straightforward statements themselves rather than the more complicated structures I am suggesting.

One important point about all such cases is that we are not asserting what we merely suppose, or what we say follows from a supposition. If I say, "Suppose Manley had won the last election in Jamaica, we would have devalued the currency" I am not asserting that Manley did win the last election (indeed I am in this case giving away the fact that I know he didn't by using the verb forms "had won...would have") nor am I asserting that we did devalue (although we did). If I say, "If Mrs. Thatcher wins again, I'll despair of human rationality" I am not asserting that she will, or that she will not, win again, nor am I making any unconditional predictions about what I will do. In both cases I only assert something within the scope of a supposition.

To indicate this suspension of commitment, I shall enclose the entertained portion of an argument within a boundary of asterisks. Let us see how this works by picturing the following argument by M.K. Bacchus:

(22) If the present situation of extremely wide income differentials between occupations continues, the process of selection for jobs will become an even more vexing issue. The assessment of work performance and aptitude, especially since the validity of aptitude tests has, so far, left much to be desired, will be a matter in which the subjective impressions of a supervisor will be crucial. [12]

What does Bacchus directly assert here? I think the only clear assertion is that the validity of aptitude tests has so far left much to be desired; the other claims are made within the supposition that wide income differentials remain. The main part of the second sentence he says follows from it; it is what makes job selection that much more vexing an issue. I suggest therefore that we should draw its structure diagram thus:

(23) a = The present situation of extremely wide income differentials between occupations continues.

b = The process of selection for jobs will become an even more vexing issue.

c = The assessment of work performance and aptitude will be a matter in which the subjective impressions of a supervisor will be crucial.

d = The validity of aptitude tests has so far left much to be desired.


*************************

* a ) *

* ) *

*****)* --> c --> b *

)*******************

d )

As often with real arguments, there may be residual doubts about the structure. In this case perhaps Bacchus is suggesting that whatever the validity of aptitude tests, still the assessment of work performance will be a matter in which subjective impressions are crucial, given the present income differentials; so we should have two arrows, one from "a" and the other from "d" to "c". But while constructing structure diagrams forces us to consider such possibilities, the main point at present is to see why most of the argument is within the asterisks - because, in this passage, Bacchus is not saying income differentials will continue or that job selection will become a more vexed issue, he is only saying if the first then the second.

There are two points worth noting now. The first is that often a writer only says "if p then q" but can be understood as tacitly asserting the "p" as well. When that happens she is also to be understood as asserting the "q" absolutely and not only within the scope of some supposition. In fact, it is quite likely that this is happening in Bacchus' argument, especially since he would not be risking much in asserting that extremely wide income differentials will continue, but what he explicitly says and what forms an essential part of whatever else he might be hinting at is as I have diagrammed it above. The second point relates to our diagrams. Since we are using arrows inside asterisks to picture entertained arguments and conditional statements it is worth noting that the arrows may here have a very weak sense. They show that something is being asserted within the scope of a supposition, but not necessarily that the supposition gives one the main grounds or even a good reason for asserting it.

Since many generalisations can be paraphrased in terms of conditional statements or entertained arguments, and since it is usually illuminating to break up sentences into smaller sentences for the purposes of argument analysis, you are likely to find that entertained arguments keep cropping up in your analyses. Thus a claim like "All acids taste sour" could be treated as one sentence in a diagram, but it might reveal more if we paraphrase it thus: "If any substance is an acid, then it is sour" or "Suppose a substance is an acid, then it is sour." These paraphrases would then be diagrammed as entertained arguments. Notice that we have various ways of expressing general claims. We could, for instance, equally well have said "An acid tastes sour."

A frequent and important use of entertained arguments is in what we may call indirect or reductio ad absurdum proofs. In these you argue for a claim by supposing its opposite and showing that this supposition leads to absurdity, usually self-contradiction. In such cases the point of the supposition is to be able eventually to assert something fully outside the scope of the supposition. It is an important form of argument in mathematics, but also in everyday life. For an everyday example, consider this argument (due to J.L. Mackie):

(24) You think I'm a swindler. But I've had $1,000 of your money for three days, and I could have walked off with it safely. But I'm still here.

Notice the rephrasing and additions in the structure diagram:

(25) a = I'm a swindler.

b = I've had $1,000 of your money for three days.

c = I could have walked off with your money safely.

d = I did walk off with your money.


************************

* a ) *

*****)* *

b )* --> d * )

)****************** ) [ ---> not a ]

c ) not d )

What happens is that the speaker asserts "b" and "c" and claims that these, together with the supposition that he is a swindler, lead to the conclusion that he would have walked off with your money; but he obviously hasn't walked off, and this, together with the whole previous argument, leads to a denial of the supposition that the speaker is a swindler (which is left for you to fill in - I have put the unstated part of the argument within square brackets). The supposition that he is a swindler has led to the absurdity of believing on the one hand that he has walked off with your money and on the other that he hasn't, since he is still here; so you must reject the supposition.

One of the reasons, besides simple accuracy, that we need to note when a claim is merely entertained and when it is genuinely endorsed relates to the kinds of critical response that are appropriate. If I tell you that Mary is at home, and give as my reason that there is a light on in the kitchen, then it is very sensible for you to object, "But there isn't a light on in the kitchen." But if I say "If Manley wins there will be another devaluation" you don't help the discussion by saying that he won't. Why not? Because here, as in very many such cases of entertained arguments or conditional statements, what is said is sustained by some other claims that the arguer may or may not be able to articulate precisely. In fact, the usefulness of these linguistic resources arises out of the fact that very often we cannot specify very exactly what these sustaining claims might be. (That is also the usefulness of the device we met long ago, in example (1), of talking about the look of clouds instead of having to say how they looked.) So, in the example we are using, my claim about what will happen if Manley wins invokes some connection between political and economic facts, but not one that I could easily state or defend explicitly. Using a conditional statement, or offering an entertained argument, is often a way of appealing to some such connection without having to bring it out explicitly. So disagreeing with such statements or arguments requires that you criticize the connection rather than pick irrelevantly on the supposition. Whether Manley wins or loses, the connection I am appealing to may exist, and it is that that I am in a sense really concerned about; so instead of irrelevantly saying that my supposition is false, you have to say something like "Even if Manley wins, there still won't be a devaluation" - that is one way of denying the connection I am appealing to. This feature is more obvious with the kind of conditional we met earlier where the arguer makes it clear she already knows the supposition is false, as when she says "If Dukakis had won, then shares would have fallen." Here objecting that Dukakis didn't win is a total waste of time since it has already been tacitly admitted. Taking the disucssion further requires us to attend to other factors.

In terms of our structure diagrams, rejecting a conditional statement or an entertained argument can be indicated simply by writing "not" in front of the whole argument in asterisks. It should be noted that this is so whenever someone denies that certain premises support a conclusion. Thus in a debate someone may assert "a" and go on to infer "b"; if you reject the inference you have to say "It is not the case that if a then b", so that part of the argument is diagrammed with a "not" in front of an argument in asterisks.

If you accept the conditional statement or the entertained argument there are two main things you can do next. You could go on to assert the statement that you had merely supposed, and that would licence you to assert what had previously been asserted only within the supposition. So if I say "If you have enjoyed reading this booklet so far, you will enjoy doing formal logic" and you reply "I have enjoyed reading this booklet so far" I am stuck with asserting "You will enjoy doing formal logic." The other thing you could do, if you accept a conditional statement or an entertained argument, is to deny what follows from the supposition, and this licences you to go on to deny the supposition. We met this strategy in the reductio ad absurdum argument, where the arguer deliberately chooses a supposition so that it can be categorically denied as the conclusion of the reasoning, but it is a general point - if we agree that something follows from a supposition but that the something is false, we can argue to the falsity of the supposition. This is a tremendously fruitful mode of argument - if it was the butler who killed the secretary his shoes would be muddy, but his shoes aren't muddy, so it wasn't the butler - and not just in detective stories. It is at the root of our attempts to understand the world we live in.

Before trying to analyse any arguments yourselves with this new tool, let us work through one further example. It is taken from a paragraph of advice on running a state, and we shall break it up to get a better grip on what is going on. Here are the first two sentences:

(26) The best fortress is to be found in the love of the people, for although you may have fortresses they will not save you if you are hated by the people. When once the people have taken arms against you, there will never be lacking foreigners to assist them. [13]

Let us take this sentence by sentence. The first sentence involves four separate ideas that we can write as separate sentences in the structure diagram:

(27) a = The best fortress is in the love of people.

b = You have fortresses.

c = Your fortresses will not save you.

d = You are hated by the people.


*********************

* b ) *

* ) ---> c * ---> a

* d ) *

*********************

The structure diagram shows that the first sentence asks the reader to make two suppositions together: you have fortresses and you are hated by your subjects. The author then says that if you suppose these two conditions your fortresses will not save you ("c"), and that entertained argument is his reason for his original assertion that the best fortress is to be found in the love of the people. The second sentence quoted above explains more fully why your fortresses won't help you - if you suppose the people have taken arms against you, there will always be outsiders prepared to help them. If we add these ideas to the diagram, we must incorporate the claim about the people taking arms as a further supposition, so it goes inside the asterisks, but the other claim is made absolutely so it goes outside thus:

(28) e = The people take arms against you.

f = There are always foreigners to assist the people.

    *********************
    * b ) *
    * ) *
    * d ) ---> c * ---> a
    * ) *
    * e ) *
    ****)****************
    )
    f )

The passage goes on to review contemporary experience to show that it fits in with the claims already analysed:

(29) In our times we do not see that they have profited any ruler, except the Countess of Forli on the death of her consort Count Girolamo, for she was enabled to escape the popular rising and await help from Milan and recover the state; the circumstances being then such that no foreigner could assist the people. But afterwards they were of little use to her when Cesare Borgia attacked her and the people being hostile to her allied themselves with the foreigner. So that then and before it would have been safer for her not to have been hated by the people than to have had the fortresses. [13]

Here, as is usual when evidence is being presented, there are quite a lot of different claims, but the pattern of argument should be fairly clear. Having argued for the general claim labelled "a" the author says that contemporary history supports it with one exception. But he goes on to add that the exception happened because on that occasion no foreigners could intervene - which we must take to be a very unusual circumstance. The usual course of events, and his generalization, are exemplified by the same Countess' later misfortune when attacked by Cesare Borgia. In diagramming these two arguments I shall use letters that reflect the claims in the original argument the evidence illustrates:

(30) a'' = The Countess of Forli would have been safer if she had not been hated by her people.

b' = The Countess of Forli had fortresses.

c' = The Countess' fortresses did not save her, the first time.

c'' = The Countess' fortresses did not save her, the second time.

d' = The Countess was hated by the people.

e' = The Countess was attacked by the people.

f' = There were foreigners to assist the people, the first time.

f'' = There were foreigners to assist the people, the second time.


On the death of her consort: b' )

)

d' )

) ---> not c' )

e' ) )

) )

not f' ) )

) ---> a''

When Cesare Borgia attacked: b' ) )

) )

d' ) ---> e' ---> c'' )

)

f'')

Note that we don't need asterisks here since all these historical claims are being asserted. You might note that the claim labelled "a''" is itself a conditional statement and so could have been further decomposed into an entertained argument. (We might have let "a'" stand for "The Countess of Forli was safe" and then replaced "a''" in the diagram with:


(31) **************************

* *

* not d' -----> a' *

* *

**************************

This is closer to the entire text, but our main concern is with the first two sentences. Note that we have not really done justice to the comparative claims in the last sentence of the original text.) If we wanted to draw one diagram for the whole passage, one could have all this historical section pointing towards "a" in (28) since the historical data are meant to be supporting that conclusion; but there is no need to combine diagrams once you grasp what is going on in the different parts and how those parts fit together. We have produced a fairly complicated picture (and there are questions of interpretation that I haven't gone into) for a fairly simple part of a paragraph, but don't be downheartened: taking things bit by bit should allow you to see the simple connections that get put together to form these sorts of structure.

EXERCISE C

Draw a labelled structure diagram for each of the following arguments:

1. If Pluto had a diameter of more than 4,200 miles, then an occultation would have occurred at McDonald Observatory, and the records clearly indicated that it did not. Thus Pluto must be that size or smaller; it cannot be larger. [14] [Answer.]

2. If we had not rushed into the development of atomic power, we would not be facing the risk of annihilation today. Would it not be better to learn from experience and proceed into the field of genetics with more caution instead of discounting all questioning voices as "alarmists"? [43] [Answer.]

3. One cannot be forced to do what one cannot do, and one cannot do what one is not free to do. Hence one is free to do what one is forced to do. [15] [Answer.]

4. In truth, there never was any remarkable lawgiver amongst any people who did not resort to divine authority, as otherwise his laws would not have been accepted by the people; for there are many good laws, the importance of which is known to the sagacious lawgiver, but the reasons for which are not sufficiently evident to enable him to persuade others to submit to them; and therefore do wise men, for the purpose of removing this difficulty, resort to divine authority. [16] [Answer.]

5. Redi demonstrated that the worms in putrefying flesh were larvae from the eggs of flies. His proofs were as simple as they were decisive, for he showed that surrounding the putrefying flesh with fine gauze absolutely prevented the appearance of these larvae. [17] [Answer.]

6. Medical science is steadily increasing the expectation of life and this, combined with the concentration of industry into larger and larger units, is having the effect that an ever greater proportion of the final power of decision is being concentrated into the hands of very old men, which is the worst possible way of facing the problems of a rapidly changing future. Since those who hold offices of power will never willingly give them up, I believe there is only one solution to this problem. The young must somehow or other enforce quite arbitrary rules of early retirement. [18] [Answer.]

7. The relative freedom we enjoy depends on public opinion. The law is no protection. Governments make laws, but whether they are carried out, and how the police behave, depends on the general temper of the country. If large numbers of people are interested in freedom of speech, there will be freedom of speech, even if the law forbids it; if public opinion is sluggish, inconvenient minorities will be persecuted, even if laws exist to protect them. [44] [Answer.]

8. Had every man sufficient sagacity to perceive, at all times, the strong interest which binds him to the observance of justice and equity, and strength of mind sufficient to persevere in a steady adherence to a general and a distant interest, in opposition to the allurements of present pleasure and advantage; there had never, in that case, been any such thing as government or political society, but each man, following his natural liberty, had lived in entire peace and harmony with all others.... It is evident, that, if government were totally useless, it never could have place, and that the sole foundation of the duty of allegiance is the advantage, which it procures to society, by preserving peace and order among mankind. [19] [Answer.]

9. Let ABC be a triangle having the angle ABC equal to the angle ACB;

I say that the side AB is also equal to the side AC.

For, if AB is unequal to AC, one of them is greater.

Let AB be greater; and from AB the greater let DB be cut off equal to AC the less; let DC be joined.

Then, since DB is equal to AC, and BC is common, the two sides DB, BC are equal to the two sides AC, CB respectively;

and the angle DBC is equal to the angle ACB;

therefore the base DC is equal to the base AB, and the triangle DBC will be equal to the triangle ACB, the less to the greater; which is absurd.

Therefore AB is not unequal to AC; it is therefore equal to it.

Therefore, if in a triangle two angles be equal to one another, the sides which subtend the equal angles will also be equal to one another. [20] [Answer.]

5. DISCUSSIONS, EXPLICIT AND IMPLICIT

So far we have considered arguments in monologue. A single speaker or writer is putting forward her train of reasoning. But we should also consider arguments of the sort that require at least two protagonists, i.e. discussions or disputes.

The crudest and least profitable kind of dialogue consists merely of counter-assertions: one speaker says one thing, the other says the opposite, and each merely repeats his own claim. A notorious intellectual vice is for the interlocutors to say that it is just a matter of individual opinion, and leave it at that. There are some matters which are indeed merely matters of individual (subjective) opinion or taste. But in any context in which it is worth discussing or trying to argue a point, there is usually a lot of ground to be covered and critically examined before one should agree to give up rational persuasion in this way. Of course, a man, or a woman for that matter, might not consent to continue the argument, to continue probing the ins and outs of a problem, but obstinacy is no reason to suppose that there is nothing to be said, nothing for critical thought to achieve. But I am in danger of digressing from our path; let us return to serious argument.

If a person puts up an argument, there are various rational possibilities open to others. In the first place, they may simply accept what has been said, premises and conclusion. This is often eminently sensible, and I hope that you don't get the mistaken impression from this booklet that you should always be searching for holes in what someone has said. Though on the other hand it must be admitted that much argument and discussion on matters of general social and political importance, such as education and schooling, is remarkably feeble.

But if you are not inclined to swallow what someone has put forward, what may you do? In the first place, you may try to rebut the argument, which requires that you deprive its conclusion of the support the argument offers it. There are two ways of doing this: either you deny vital premises (and possibly produce arguments of your own to show that these premises are unacceptable) or you challenge the strength of the link between premises and conclusion (saying in effect, I can accept your premises but they don't serve to support your conclusion). We shall look soon at some of the issues that arise in criticizing the kind of support involved in an argument. In the second place, however, you may put forward a counter-argument of your own for a different conclusion, a conclusion in conflict with that of the first speaker. A full reply to the speaker requires that you do both of these things. If you only rebut her argument, you deprive her conclusion of the support she offered it (in effect, you deny her right to continue believing the conclusion), but it might yet be correct, and you have done nothing to show that it isn't. If you only put forward a counter-argument, we are left with two arguments in the field, but with no guide as to how to decide between them.

The result of an intelligent reply to an argument is likely to be that new points of disagreement come to light. The rational thing to do is to carry on the discussion by taking up these new matters and looking for ways of resolving the issues one way or the other.

People do on occasions discuss matters with one another, and one could analyse their dialogue along the lines suggested. Sometimes people present their ideas by means of a fictional dialogue - in philosophy we have the many dialogues written by Plato, as well as some notable examples by Berkeley and Hume. Here is an extract from a short passage of such imaginary dialogue on a philosophical topic:

(32) Until recently, debates about materialism have gone something like this:

Hylas: Since science seems to need to talk about nothing save atoms and the void in order to explain everything that happens, only atoms and the void are really real.

Philonous: But what is science save a scheme for ordering our experiences? Or, if it is more than this, how can it possibly deny that it rests upon experiences, and that these experiences are something different from either the atoms or the void?

H: What you call 'experience' is but another name for bounding atoms in the brain.

P: That is the sort of thing one would only say if one were defending a theory at all costs. What criterion of 'same' could one possibly use to show that two such different things were the same?

H: Two things are the same thing if talking about the one serves all the purposes as talking about the other. [45]

In this fragment (the author continued with four more speeches) we can see several of the points made above about what can happen in serious debate. But note that several contributions are either straightforward questions or rhetorical questions which we must translate into the simple assertion implied. Here is a possible diagram of the argument:

(33) a = Science only needs atoms and the void to explain everything.

b = Only atoms and the void are real.

c = Science explains (or is supported by) experience.

d = Experiences are different from atoms and the void.

e = Experiences are atoms moving in the brain.

f = X is the same as Y.

g = Talk about X serves all the purposes of talk about Y.



1 H: a --------> b

2 P: c )

) [-----> not b ]

d )

3 H: e [-------> not d ]

4 P: What criterion for f in this case?

5 H: *************************

* *

* g --------> f *

* *

*************************

You can see clearly here how many of the intermediate conclusions are left unstated by each of the speakers, and I have left out the fairly complicated unstated extras needed for the last remark: talk of atoms in the brain serves all the purposes of talk of experiences so experiences just are such atoms in motion. We do not have the tools to deal adequately with the last part of the dialogue, but you can see that in the earlier part the moves link up with each other in the way we mentioned above and that P's question in turn 4 is asked in the hope of showing that H's claim in 3, "e", is false. H in turn 5 assumes that the general principle applies to the case in point, and the debate then goes on (in the original) by discussing that unstated claim.

While we can find explicit dialogue in some writings, much more commonly people develop their ideas through a sort of implicit dialogue. They argue for a position not only by presenting a case for it, but often more importantly by attacking other positions or by imagining objections to their own view and replying to them. Writing on controversial topics is very often shot through with such implicit dialogue, and sometimes it is difficult to disentangle the resulting fabric of thought, to tell when the author is speaking in her own voice, as it were, and when through the mouth of an imagined opponent. But, as with structure diagrams in general, it is a worthwhile exercise to try sometimes to formulate explicitly the backwards and forwards movement of thought in a passage, or indeed in a whole article or book.

Although it can be difficult to disentangle a passage, in many cases there will be clues in the text to suggest which parts belong to which voice. Very frequently a speaker or writer will explicitly attribute some opinion to other people and then tell us her own, usually different view. Jesus is portrayed as making the contrast: "Ye have heard that it was said by them of old time .... But I say unto you...." Other writers often tell you what "most people" think, or expound what "is commonly believed" before launching into their own refinements or opposing views. In the following passage the author distinguishes two views, one held by the ancients, the other by his contemporaries. Since he gives reasons for both views it can simplify our task of describing his argumentation to separate the two bits of reasoning as shown in the diagram:

(34) Tyrannicide, or the assassination of usurpers and oppressive princes, was highly extolled in ancient times; because it both freed mankind from many of these monsters, and seemed to keep others in awe, whom the sword or poinard could not reach. But history and experience have since convinced us, that this practice increases the jealousy and cruelty of princes; a Timoleon and a Brutus, though treated with indulgence on account of the prejudices of their time, are now considered as very improper models for imitiation. [46]

(35) a = Tyrannicide is admirable.

b = Tyrannicide frees us from oppression.

c = Tyrannicide deters some rulers.

d = Tyrannicide increases the cruelty of princes.


Ancients: b )

) -----------> a

c )

Hume: d ----> [ not c ] ---> not a

This diagram may be rather insensitive, but my main point is that any attempt to present the passage as a monologue would be messier and less sensitive. Note, for instance, that Hume does not clearly commit himself even to a conditional endorsement of tyrannicide - if it frees mankind from some oppressors and deters others then tyrannicide is admirable - but this would seem the only way to treat this part of the text if it is taken as one continuous argument.

Let us work through the following example:

(36) In a discussion of flight training, experienced instructors noted that praise for an exceptionally smooth landing is typically followed by a poorer landing on the next try, while harsh criticism after a rough landing is usually followed by an improvement on the next try. The instructors concluded that verbal rewards are detrimental to learning, while verbal punishments are beneficial, contrary to accepted psychological doctrine. This conclusion is unwarranted because of the presence of regression toward the mean. As in other cases of repeated examination, an improvement will usually follow a poor performance and a deterioration will usually follow an outstanding performance, even if the instructor does not respond to the trainee's achievement on the first attempt. Because the instructors had praised their trainees after good landings and admonished them after poor ones, they reached the erroneous and potentially harmful conclusion that punishment is more effective than reward. [21]

Here we have two main protagonists, experienced flight instructors and the authors of the passage, though the psychological establishment gets an aside which is, however, not really relevant to the argument in this passage. (That is to say, the authors' argument is independent of the psychological doctrine in question, though their argument serves to support it by refuting a bad argument against it.) The passage begins by reporting the kind of thinking used by the experienced instructors; it then says that this kind of reasoning fails because of something called "regression toward the mean", and it immediately goes on to illustrate what that amounts to. The final sentence sums up the erroneous reasoning again, and can be left out of our structure diagram.

If we rewrite the passage as a dialogue we might get something like this:

(37) Instructors: Praise is typically followed by a worse landing; harsh criticism is usually followed by a better landing. So punishment works better than reward.

Psychology (offstage): No! Rewards promote learning more than punishments.

The Authors: You have been misled by regression toward the mean. Deterioration usually follows a good performance; improvement usually follows a bad performance, whether or not the instructor says anything. So it doesn't follow that punishment is more effective than reward.

So far this is fairly clear since the authors illustrate what they mean by regression toward the mean. The basic logical structure underlying the dialogue is, however, somewhat complicated; the authors do not deny that things happen in the sequence the instructors have noticed, but they do deny that the instructors have found the correct causal explanation for that sequence. One way of bringing out the fundamental ideas might be this:

(38) a = There is a good landing.

b = The instructor praises.

c = The next landing is worse.

d = There is a bad landing.

e = The instructor criticizes.

f = The next landing is better.

g = The facts mentioned in "b" and "e" are crucial for learning how to fly, in particular verbal punishment is more effective than reward.


Instructors: *****************

* a ) * )

* ) ---> c * )

* b ) * )

***************** )

) ---> g

***************** )

* d ) * )

* ) ---> f * )

* e ) * )

*****************

Authors: ***************** )

* a ) * )

* ) ---> c * )

* not b) * )

***************** )

) ---> not g

***************** )

* d ) * )

* ) ---> f * )

* not e) * )

*****************

Notice that I have put most of the evidence inside asterisks: suppose there is a good landing and the instructor praises it then the next one is worse. It wouldn't matter here if one regarded the evidence as asserted: when there is a good landing.... Notice that in either case, the arrow is very weak; it doesn't stand for strong reason-given support, merely as a way of picturing what is asserted on certain grounds. Defining the conclusion, "g", in the way I have (saying roughly if b then c and if e then f) allows the authors' argument to lead to "not g" as it seems to in the passage, although the real force of their argument is to reject the instructors' reasoning from evidence to causal claim rather than to reject that causal claim itself.

Let us close this section of our study by examining the exchange implicit in the following passage by Jacques Barzun, on a topic that is pertinent to our own concerns in this course:

(39) More than one school catalogue I have read begins by saying: 'At the -- School, the first of our objectives is to encourage students to think for themselves.' The redundancy gives away the pretense: encourage them, equip them, to think, and much will have been done. Whoever thinks does it by himself and for himself. But to encourage the utterance of opinion unchecked does nothing to encourage thought. Rather, it strengthens the prejudice against thought, by persuading each child that everybody is entitled to his own opinion, 'especially me to mine'. [22]

On the surface, Barzun reports what he has heard and then goes on to comment on it, but we can bring out his thought by seeing it as a dialogue: a school spokesman says "The first of our objectives is to encourage students to think for themselves" and Barzun scornfully replies, "You lie. Whoever thinks does it by himself and for himself. But you encourage the utterance of unchecked opinion, so you persuade children that everyone is entitled to their own opinion, so you strengthen the prejudice against thought." This omits Barzun's further comment that equipping people to think would be a fine thing, if done properly, and a few other smaller points; but the main thing is to see the dialogue implicit in the development of Barzun's argument.

EXERCISE D

Draw structure diagrams of the following passages, bearing in mind the possibility of implicit dialogue:

1. In Africa, even though the total number of drop-outs at the start of the school career appears to have fallen, there has in most cases been an increase in repeaters, indicating that educational prospects at the beginning of the school career have not really improved. [23] [Answer.]

2. It may be going too far to say that the unexamined life is not worth living, but if reason and wisdom have any value then such a life will be less than satisfactory. [47] [Answer.]

3. The view that romantic love is essential to marriage is too anarchic, and, like St Paul's view, though in an opposite sense, it forgets that children are what makes marriage important. But for children, there would be no need of any institution concerned with sex, but as soon as children enter in, the husband and wife, if they have any offspring, are compelled to realise that their feelings towards each other are no longer what is of most importance. [48] [Answer.]

4. Nationalism and socialism are incompatible for a number of reasons. First, the basis of all nationalist theories is that those supposed to make up a "nation" have a common interest. This is not true. All "nations" are divided into two antagonistic classes. Between these classes is an irreconcilable conflict of interest which can only be resolved by the conversion of the means of production into the common property of the whole community, by the dispossession of the owning class. Nationalism also assumes that the problems facing the non-owning class can be solved on a national scale, within the borders of a particular state. This is quite wrong. Capitalism is the cause of these problems. And since capitalism is a system existing all over the world it can only be abolished on a world scale. [24] [Answer.]

5. By far the commonest argument for discriminating against women takes the line that women are to be excluded because they are not equal to the task in question. They cannot be dockers or bus drivers because they are not strong enough,.... The usual feminist response to this line is an indignant denial of the whole thing: either the accusations are false, or if women are in some ways inferior to men it is because men have deprived women of proper education. There is of course much truth in this. However, this is one clear case in which feminists would do better to forget about factual argument for a while and concentrate on the logic. This reasoning is absolutely absurd for two reasons. In the first place, nearly all the differences claimed to exist between men and women are differences of average.... Second, even if there were cases where it looked as though all women actually might be worse at something than all men, that still would not account for a rule specifically excluding them or saying they should do better than men to be admitted, because, as Mill said, 'What women by nature cannot do, it is quite superfluous to forbid them from doing. What they can do, but not so well as the men who are their competitors, competition suffices to exclude them from...' [25] [Answer.]

6. Writers, philosophers and artists eat food that others have grown and use energy that others have worked to provide, and perhaps do not think enough about the value of what is given back. This line of thought tends to push intellectual activity low down the list of priorities, as the marginal luxury of the comfortable. But I hope that some of the considerations suggested by the thought experiments [in earlier chapters of the book] will check this tendency. These activities are not a dispensable frill, but are central to some of the values that give life a focus and a centre, once basic needs for food, shelter and health have been satisfied. Some of the values - relationships between men and women, parents and children, which can be of a quite unintellectual kind - are at least as important. But even here, relationships change with ways of thinking and seeing. So, if writers and others do interesting work, perhaps something is given back. Though this too may be self-deception. [26] [Answer.]

7. The idea that competition is vicious has been challenged by several writers. Every person, they say, is good at something, and failure in one area is counterbalanced by success in another. Thus, each person will find a context in which he/she will find self-esteem, accceptance, and a sense of achievement. This competitive pluralism must be acknowledged; no doubt it serves to ameliorate the effects of competition for personal goods. Nevertheless, the argument overlooks the differential status which is accorded to these competitive arrangements. Success in certain kinds of competition is accorded considerable social standing, giving those who do well wide acceptance and manoeuvrability, whereas those who succeed in less vaunted enterprises may find their acceptance limited to a very small group of people, who anyway wish for success in the more highly ranked enterprises. [49] [Answer.]

6. VARIETIES OF SUPPORT

So far we have looked at the overall pattern of simple arguments, and noted some of the intricacies in what an arguer is actually committed to. We have been mainly concerned with how to describe arguments. In this and the next few sections we shall turn to the kind of support premises give to conclusions, and our interest will be mainly evaluative. But first let us attempt to describe, or at least indicate, the two radically different kinds of support that I shall follow tradition in distinguishing.

Consider two pieces of reasoning. Suppose that the first time I arrived in Trinidad the first people I saw were all Indian. I might then have argued from the fact that I had seen ten people in Trinidad and that they were all Indian to the conclusion all Trinidadians are Indian. (You may think such an argument unbelievably silly, but many of my compatriots have beliefs about West Indians and Pakistanis that are no better based.) Now what kind of argument have I got here? I surely cannot rely very much on it; I really ought to be prepared to qualify or even radically alter my conclusion in the light of further evidence. (Suppose my first ten Trinidadians were all male, or over 16 years old; it would be almost impossible for the whole population to be like that.) So while we may allow that my premise gives some support to the conclusion, we must insist that it is precious little.

Suppose instead that I am assured that no Muslims eat pork wittingly and that I see a man order and eat some pork chops, I may then argue that the man is not a Muslim. What kind of argument have I now? My premises are that no Muslims wittingly eat pork, and that this man is wittingly eating pork. Given these two premises, surely I can't go wrong in claiming that this man is not a Muslim. (Of course, my premises might be mistaken; but so might my claims about my first ten Trinidadians - in looking at both specimen arguments we are not disputing the truth of their premises.) In this second type of argument, my premises give a kind of guarantee to the conclusion. The guarantee is not that my conclusion is true (we've noted already that my premises may be wrong), but rather that if my premises are true then my conclusion will be true too; I can't have true premises and a false conclusion. It is a conditional guarantee of truth. In this sort of argument, truth is transmitted, as it were, from the premises to the conclusion.

But equally important, this sort of argument transmits falsehood from the conclusion back to the premises taken together. Staying with our pork-eater, if he really is a Muslim then either he is not wittingly eating pork or it is false that no Muslims eat pork wittingly (as usually in this booklet, either/or allows both).

So, then, we have found two different sorts of support: one which is simply support and which doesn't offer any guarantees (in particular, it allows the premises to be true and the conclusion false), and one which incorporates a conditional guarantee that you can't have the premises true and the conclusion false. From here on things get a bit messy, both because we are beginning to cut below the surface of our reasoning and because, annoyingly, terminology is somewhat unsettled. But let me stipulate how I propose to talk: basically arguers put up arguments, and I shall classify arguments by the kind of support the arguer supposes them to have, (the first sort I shall call "non-deductive"; the one with the conditional guarantee, I shall call "deductive") and also, if necessary, by whether they do embody that kind of support (the ones that do I shall call "valid", the ones that do not I shall call "invalid").

My way of talking allows for four types of argument:

    (a) valid deductive (e.g. No communists are Christians, so no Christians are communists);
    (b) invalid deductive (e.g. All communists are atheists, so all atheists are communists);
    (c) valid non-deductive (e.g. The mortality ratios for lung cancer for smokers and non-smokers are statistically significantly different, and the ratio for smokers is greater than 1, so smoking is a causal factor for getting lung cancer);
    (d) invalid non-deductive (e.g. Most communists are atheists, so most atheists are communists).

Note that all non-deductive arguments are deductively invalid; some writers restrict "valid" and "invalid" to deductive arguments. Note also that some invalid arguments are often called "fallacies" (though in some cases what people call fallacies are perfectly valid arguments which the people dislike for some other reason). Note, finally, that many writers contrast deductive with inductive arguments; by "inductive" they may mean what I mean by "non-deductive" or some more restricted kind of argument (e.g. from singular premises to another singular conclusion - The first swan was white, the second swan was white,... so the next swan will be white - or from singular premises to some kinds of generalization - The first swan was white, the second was white,...so all (most) swans are white).

While dealing with my stipulation about the meaning of "valid", it is worth noting another and more general stipulation in logical analysis. Arguments can be described as valid or invalid, but that pair has no sense when applied to the statements, sentences or propositions making up an argument. Those statements etc. can be true or false, but not valid or invalid. Conversely, there is no sense in talking about arguments as true or false.

The point of this section is to distinguish deductive from non-deductive arguments. It is important to decide which sort of argument you are dealing with. The question is, in effect, whether the arguer supposes she can rely on the deductive guarantee - no possible situation in which the premises are true and the conclusion false. If she thinks she can, you have a fairly clear-cut issue as we shall see; but if she isn't relying on a deductive link, things are less clear. It would be nice if it were always obvious which kind of argument was in question, but unfortunately it isn't. There are at least two reasons for this, and they may overlap in some cases.

The first reason is that you can always convert a non-deductive argument into a valid deductive argument by adding extra premises. This, as it stands, is not much of a reason for finding the distinction hazy, but it is strengthened when you note that often a non-deductive argument can be transformed into a valid deductive one by adding obvious and plausible extra premises, such as an arguer might well leave out, as being too obvious or well-known to her audience. If I simply said to you "Ade eats pork, so she's not a Muslim" my one explicit premise only gives non-deductive support to my conclusion; but I could well be relying on an unstated premise that no Muslims eat pork, and with that my argument becomes deductively valid. So we have here the general problem of knowing how much to add to what gets explicitly stated in an argument.

The second sort of reason is that people may not be clear in their own minds what kind of argument they are using. After all, I have had to explain the distinction to you, and you may not yet grasp it properly. Let us look back at one of the examples I offered above - most communists are atheists, so most atheists are communists. I said this was a non-deductive argument, but some arguers might well treat it as deductive - they often behave as if the analogous argument with "all" replacing "most" is valid deductively, and the argument with "some" replacing "most" is valid deductively, so I agree that some people might treat it as a deductive argument. But I think that it is also possible for someone to realize that this argument is deductively invalid, but think it was a reasonable gamble, non-deductively. At this point, the first sort of problem might begin to arise since such a reasoner might not be arguing only from the premise that most communists are atheists, but also from a collection of other unstated premises about the distribution of the various religions, the strength of secularism in different parts of the world, and so on. (Analogous points could be made about the other example of an invalid argument above.) Again, while no one, I hope, would imagine that noting the race, colour, sex, or other salient characteristics of the first ten people they see in Trinidad would give them a reliable basis for generalization, many people do seem to treat the measurement of characteristics in a more scientific setting as if it were the direct establishment of a universal generalization, rather than a report of what was found for a minute sample under a certain range of conditions. You might measure the velocity of sound in a slim steel rod at a certain temperature, pressure, etc. and we might (erroneously in this case) suppose that you have established the velocity of sound in steel. When people are unclear, then if our concern is simply with describing the person's argument, we have to say they are unclear, but if our concern is with the actual issues rather than the arguer, then we have to decide how much revision of the argument we can allow, since the temptation here is to reconstruct the reasoning in the light of what we think the actual logical relations are. And as far as pursuing the issues goes, it may not be a bad thing to succumb to this temptation.

We have come several times upon the question of what unstated premises to add to an explicit argument. What should we do? There is no hard and fast answer, but there are a few points to note. The first I have just mentioned: we are usually more interested in the argument than the arguer. We have seen already that we talk a lot about what we and other people may be thinking, but our real concerns are not with the psychological histories of individuals, but with the matters they think about. So rather than try to specify the often somewhat indeterminate thoughts a person may have had, it is usually better, and easier, to specify the possibilities for the argument. And this amounts to looking for extra premises that are sufficient to make it a valid argument, and asking whether they are plausible. In some cases, such as the little argument already noted "Ade eats pork, so she's not a Muslim," this gives us a straightforward answer - the extra premise "No Muslims eat pork" is fairly widely known, is supposed to be true, and does no harm to the argument, indeed it makes it deductively valid. But in other cases, people make mistakes, and looking at the alternatives can help you to uncover them. Suppose McCarthy had argued "Ade's not a Christian, so she's a communist." Here we have a common sort of case where both obvious construals of the argument fail, but for different reasons. What would make the argument deductively valid? The premise "All non-Christians are communists." If McCarthy accepted this, he would have had a valid argument; but could even McCarthy have believed so implausible a claim? What might he have believed? A premise like "All communists are non-Christians" (in English, "No communists are Christians"). Depending on how you construe this, it may or may not be true, but at least it is plausible in our context. But it doesn't entail the needed "All non-Christians are communists." So we seem to have presented McCarthy with an unattractive choice: either his argument is valid, but based on an obviously false premise, or it is deductively invalid. Either way, his stated premise does not support his conclusion. (I am assuming the argument is not intended to be simply non-deductive.)

The aim, in adding extra premises, is, as Scriven says, "to find something that's strong enough to patch up the holes in the argument, but not any stronger than it has to be" [27]; or to do the best you can and thereby reveal how the argument fails. Discovering such extra assumptions requires judgment and practice; as we have noted with other issues, there is no automatic way of doing it. The best thing is to try lots of examples.

EXERCISE E

Read the following arguments carefully (you may find it helpful to do a structure diagram) and then decide whether they are deductive or non-deductive, and consider whether any extra assumptions should be added:

(1) Most Swedes are Protestants; most Swedes who visit Lourdes are not Protestants; so most Swedes do not visit Lourdes. [28] [Answer.]

(2) The word education comes from the Latin 'educa-re' (to train, to bring up), which is related to another Latin word 'educe-re' (to lead forth, to draw out). To educate is therefore to bring up or train. [29] [Answer.]

(3) Since there are more people on the earth than hairs on any one person's head, I know that there must be at least two people with the same number of hairs. [30] [Answer.]

(4) The most economical and satisfactory way for members to buy vintage clarets is when they are first available. Not only are they then almost certain to be at their least expensive, but also the widest choice of the best wine is available. [31] [Answer.]

(5) In an earlier section of this book the strong association between 'broken homes' and delinquency was noted.... The main question is whether the harm comes from disruption of bonds or distortion of relationships. This may be considered by comparing homes broken by death... and homes broken by divorce or separation.... This comparison has been made in several independent studies.... In each case the delinquency rate has been about double (compared to that for boys in intact homes) for boys whose parents had divorced or separated, whereas the delinquency rate has been only slightly (and non-significantly) raised for those who lost a parent by death. This suggests that it may be the discord and disharmony preceding the break (rather than the break itself) which led to the children developing antisocial behaviour. [50] [Answer.]

(6) Monopoly, and the hideous accumulation of capital in a few hands, carry in their own enormity, the seeds of cure. Whatever presses men together, though it may generate some vices, is favourable to the diffusion of knowledge, and ultimately promotive of human liberty. [32] [Answer.]


Suggested Answers

EXERCISE C

1.

a = Pluto has a diameter of more than 4,200 miles.

b = An occultation occurred at McDonald Observatory.

    *******************
    * *
    * a --> b * )
    * * )
    ******************* ) --> not a
    )
    not b )

Note here that there are only two claims and their negations involved in this argument.

2. Note here the rhetorical question, instead of a straightforward assertion of the conclusion. The remark about learning from experience seems like padding, or perhaps a way of tacitly asserting what our actual situation is, which is how I have dealt with it:

a = We rushed into the development of atomic power.

b = We face the risk of annihilation.

c = We should proceed cautiously in genetics.

d = We should not discount questioners as "alarmists".

    ***********************
    * * )
    * not a ---> not b * ) ( c
    * * ) -------> (
    *********************** ) ( d
    )
    [ b ) ]

3. The simplest analysis of this argument does not involve any entertained argument, thus:

a = One cannot be forced to do what one cannot do.

b = One cannot do what one is not free to do.

c = One is free to do what one is forced to do.

    a )
    ) ------> c
    b )

This captures the surface of the argument, but does not reveal much of what is going on. The argument plays with ideas about what you can or cannot do, what you are or are not forced to do, etc. Let us write "X" for whatever doing is in question, and let us allow ourselves to use "not possible that" as well as the "not" that we have learnt to use in structure diagrams; now we can dig a lot deeper:

a = You can do X.

b = You are forced to do X.

c = You are free to do X.

    ******************************
    * *
    * not a ----> not possible * )
    * that b * ) *************
    ****************************** ) * *
    ) ---> * b ---> c *
    ****************************** ) * *
    * * ) *************
    * not c ----> not a * )
    * *
    ******************************

Take careful note of how I have translated the straightforward sentences of the original argument (which are categorical in form) into the conditional form represented here by the asterisks. For example, the conclusion said "One is free to do what one is forced to do"; this translates as "If you are forced to do X then you are free to do X" and not as "If you are free to do X then you are forced to do X." (That would be equivalent to saying that you are forced to do what you are free to do.)

Notice also, that a, b, and c are sentences, or at least quasi-sentences. The original sentences might suggest an analysis in which you let "a" equal "what you cannot do", "b" equal "what one is forced to do", and so on. The premises and conclusion would then be some sort of claim to the effect that what you cannot do includes what you are not free to do. Such an analysis might be possible, but would be a little more complicated than my second analysis. Keeping all the components declarative sentences allows us to use "not" in illuminating ways to reveal structure; in other analyses there is a danger of swallowing up such "nots".

4.

a = Wise lawgivers resort to divine authority.

b = The laws are accepted by the people.

c = The reasons for some good laws are too obscure for most people to understand.

    **************************
    * *
    * not a ) *
    * ) ---> not b * ---> a
    * ) *
    **********)***************
    )
    c )

Here I have simplified the text considerably, though I hope it is clear how the answer corresponds to the original. The entertained argument is offered as an explanation of the supposed fact that lawgivers always appeal to divine authority. Notice how much the little word "otherwise" conceals.

5. This passage is literally about Redi and his proof, but the reasoning it contains is better brought out by focussing on those "proofs". A very simple analysis avoids entertained arguments, thus:

a = The worms in putrefying flesh are larvae from the eggs of flies.

b = Surrounding the putrefying flesh with fine gauze absolutely prevents the appearance of these worms.

b ------> a

But one could break up the two main ideas of "b", and also add (inside square brackets []) the unstated normal experience that forms the background of Redi's experiment, thus:

a = The worms in putrefying flesh are larvae from the eggs of flies.

b = You surround the putrefying flesh with fine gauze.

c = Larvae appear.

    ********************
    * *
    * b ---> not c * )
    * * )
    ******************** )
    ) ---> a
    ******************** )
    * * )
    [ * not b ---> c * ] )
    * *
    ********************

6. The only major problem in this argument arises out of the talk about problems. I think the author is inviting his audience to suppose they want to face the problems of the future in the best possible way, and so I shall introduce it explicitly into the structure:

a = Medical science is steadily increasing the expectation of life.

b = Industry is being concentrated into ever larger units.

c = An ever greater proportion of the final power of decision is being concentrated into the hands of very old men.

d = We want to solve our problems in the best way.

e = Those who hold offices of power never willingly give them up.

f = The young must enforce arbitrary rules of early retirement.

    a )
    ) --> c )
    b ) ) *****************
    e )* *
    *) --> f *
    ***** ) *
    * d ) *
    **************************

I must admit that this way of handling the argument reads Leach's conclusion not as a straightforward assertion but as one merely within a supposition. Since the supposition I have offered is itself one that might well be taken for granted, you could delete it and the asterisks. Similar problems arise with much reasoning for practical proposals.

Notice here again that we can treat causal claims by rewriting them as simple arguments. This reveals more of what is happening than would have been achieved by treating the whole first sentence as a single premise.

7. Here we have a case where much of the argument for one claim is an argument against another. Most of the argument is in the last sentence, but it takes two different issues (freedom of speech and the protection of inconvenient minorities) which are, however, meant to illustrate the same point. I have therefore rolled them together in the analysis. I have also condensed the third sentence.

a = The freedom we enjoy depends on public opinion.

b = The law is no protection.

c = Law enforcement depends on public opinion.

d = Large numbers of people want freedom (of speech).

e = There is freedom (of speech).

f = Laws exist to protect (minorities).

    ***********************
    * *
    * d ) *
    * ) ---> e * )
    * not f ) * )
    * * )
    *********************** )
    ) ---> c ---> b ---> a
    *********************** )
    * * )
    * not d ) * )
    * ) ---> not e * )
    * f ) *
    * *
    ***********************

8.

a = Every man has sufficient sagacity to perceive, at all times, the strong interest which binds him to the observance of justice and equity.

b = Every man has strength of mind sufficient to persevere in a steady adherence to a general and a distant interest, in opposition to the allurements of present pleasure and advantage.

c = There is such a thing as government or civil society.

d = Each man, following his natural liberty, lives in entire peace and harmony with all others.

e = Government is totally useless.

f = The sole foundation of the duty of allegiance is the advantage which it procures to society by preserving peace and order.

The argument begins straightforwardly (suppose a and b, then never c but rather d); there is a brief argument (if e then never c) which seems to repeat the first but which is placed as if it followed from the previous considerations as clearly as does the final conclusion, f. I think the linkages here are as much implicit as explicit, so I have put them in square brackets again (note the role of the unstated c in both explicit arguments):

    *****************************
    * * )
    * a ) * )
    * ) ---> never c, but d * )
    * b ) * )
    * * )
    ***************************** ) (a ] )
    ) ---> not ( ] )
    [c ) ) (b ] ) ---> f
    ) )
    ******************** ) )
    * * )
    * e ---> never c * ) ---> not e ] )
    * * )
    ********************

In this representation, the brief lower argument is still a repetition, at a less specific level, of the more extended argument from lack of sagacity and strength of mind. One might wish to see the conditional claim "If government were totally useless, it never could have place" as an emphatic way of saying "not e", and then diagram thus:

    *******************************
    * *
    * a ) *
    * ) ---> never c, but d * ---> not e ---> f
    * b ) *
    * *
    *******************************

9. This is a fairly elementary mathematical argument (it is in fact the first reductio argument in Euclid), but it is rather complicated in its structure, especially the assumptions inside assumptions. One example can hardly prove my contention, but I hope it encourages you to consider whether perhaps mathematical reasoning is not usually too complex to be used as an introduction to rigorous argument. (And remember the following diagram does not fill in the various things Euclid leaves unstated.)

a = ABC is a triangle having the angle ABC = the angle ACB.

b = The side AB = the side AC.

c = AB is greater than AC.

d = AC is greater than AB.

e = From AB the greater, DB is cut off equal to AC the less.

f = DC is joined.

g = DB is equal to AC.

h = BC is common.

i = The two sides DB, BC, are equal to the two sides AC, CB respectively.

j = The angle DBC = the angle ACB.

k = The base DC = the base AB.

l = The triangle DBC = the triangle ACB, the less to the greater. [This is a contradiction.]

m = If in a triangle two angles are equal to one another, the sides which subtend the equal angles will also be equal to one another.

    ********************************************************
    * *
    * a ) *
    * ) *
    * *********)*************************** *
    * * ) * *
    * * ) --> either c or d * *
    * * not b ) * *
    * * * *
    * * ******************************* * *
    * * * * * *
    * * * c ) (g) (i) (k * * *
    * * * ) ( ) ( ) ( * * *
    * * * e ) --> (&) --> (&) --> (& * * *
    * * * ) ( ) ( ) ( * * *
    * * * f ) (h) (j) (l ------> not not b-->b-->m
    * * * * * *
    * * ******************************* * *
    * ************************************* *
    ********************************************************

N.B. Please note that the inner-most box of asterisks should really be placed beneath "either c or d."

Euclid leaves unstated the required parallel argumentation from the assumption of "d" to "l". These two derivations allow one to infer "Not not b" from "Either c or d."

EXERCISE D

1. The use of "even though" often indicates a possible hidden dialogue, e.g.

a = The total number of drop-outs at the start of the school career has fallen in Africa.

b = There has been in most cases an increase in repeaters.

c = Educational prospects at the beginning of the school career have improved in Africa.

African: a --> c

Author : b --> not c

This is an example of the sort of inconclusive dialogue I have discussed: we have a reason for and a reason against a particular conclusion, but so far no resolution.

2. As in many examples where a dialogue is implied, here one voice only makes a claim without any supporting argument and so to show the reasoning we could omit it; but it is necessary here at least to recognize that there is a significant difference between saying that a kind of life is not worth living and saying that it is less than satisfactory.

a = The unexamined life is not worth living.

b = Reason and wisdom have some value.

c = The unexamined life is less than satisfactory.

    Socrates: a
    Brown: *******************
    * *
    * b ----> c *
    * *
    *******************

Note that the author does not here assert "b".

3. As in the previous example, an opposing voice is suggested simply to state a claim which is then rebutted. I shall not bother to make this into a dialogue.

a = Romantic love is essential to marriage.

b = Children make marriage important.

c = There is need for an institution concerned with sex.

d = A husband and wife have children.

e = The couple's mutual feelings are not most important.

    *************************
    * *
    * not d ----> not c * )
    * * )
    ************************* )
    ) -----> b -----> not a
    ************************* )
    * * )
    * d ---> e [ --> c ] * )
    * *
    *************************

4. This piece of political argument can be seen as a rather one-sided dialogue between a nationalist and a socialist (of a certain sort). In claiming their two doctrines are compatible, the nationalist is saying he can believe both; the socialist then proceeds to argue that the crucial nationalist claims are false.

a = Nationalism and socialism are incompatible.

b = Those making up a "nation" have a common interest.

c = All "nations" are divided into two antagonistic classes.

d = There is an irreconcilable conflict of interest between these classes which can only be resolved by the dispossession of the owning class.

e = The problems facing the non-owning class can be solved on a national scale.

f = Capitalism is the cause of these problems.

g = Capitalism is a system existing all over the world.

h = Capitalism can only be abolished on a world scale.

    Nationalist: b
    )
    Socialist : c ) )
    ) --> not b ) )
    d ) )
    )
    ) --> a
    Nationalist: e )
    ) )
    Socialist : f ) )
    ) --> h --> not e )
    g )

The socialist obviously has the last word: "a". (In this case I am suggesting in the diagram that the component dialogues are themselves premises for the socialist's overall argument; this is by no means always the case when you have implicit dialogue.)

5. Here we have a discussion in three voices: a male chauvinist, a typical feminist, and the arbitration of the author, the sceptical feminist. There is quite a lot of detail, some of which has been omitted from the passage, but the overall structure is:

Male: Women are not equal to the task so we must C.P. exclude them.

Fem.: Women are equal to the task, or if not it is because men have deprived them of education.

JRR.: The feminist is correct on the whole but the male chauvinist's argument is invalid anyway: it points to average differences; and if women are really not equal to the task there is no need to exclude them.

a = Women are to be excluded from doing X.

b = Women are not equal to the task of doing X.

c = Men have deprived women of the proper education.

d = Nearly all the differences claimed to exist between men and women are differences of average.

e = It is quite superfluous to forbid women to do X.

    Male chauvinist: b ---> a
    Feminist : mostly not b --\
    \-->
    **************** not a
    * * /-->
    * b --> c * --/
    * *
    ****************
    Author : d --\
    \ **********
    \-> * *
    *************** not * b -->a *
    * * /--> * *
    * b --> e * --/ **********
    * *
    ***************

In this diagram I have left out the second half of Mill's point. In the argument I have also left out the development of the point labelled "d"; if it is not obvious, try reading the original.

6. In this brief ruminative piece we have author and critic, and at the very end the author wondering whether to adopt the critic's viewpoint. In the following rewriting I have over-dramatized and exaggerated the contrasting sides of the argument, and I have also made some debatable interpretations of the author's grammar:

Critic: Writers etc live off other people and they do not think about the value of what they give back. So their kind of activity is a marginal luxury of the comfortable.

Author: Yes, but intellectual activity is not a marginal luxury, once we have satisfied basic needs. My earlier chapters show that it is central to some of our most important values.

Critic: But there are other values, kinds of relationship, that are at least as important.

Author: But even these relationships change with ways of thinking and seeing, so if writers and others do interesting work, something is given back. But that argument too may be self-deception.

We can diagram a simplified version thus:

a = Writers etc live off other people.

b = Writers etc do not give anything back.

c = Intellectual activity is a marginal luxury.

d = Intellectual activity is central to some important values.

e = There are other values as important.

f = These values change with ways of thinking and seeing.

g = Writers etc do work on ways of thinking and seeing.

    Critic: a)
    ) ---> c
    b)
    Author: Yes, a; but
    d ---> not c ---> not b
    Critic: e
    Author: f) ******************
    ) * *
    ***)* ---> not b *
    * ) *
    * g) *
    * *
    ***********************
    ?

7. As usual, I am simplifying the claims made in this argument. The author presents an opposing view which he partially accepts ("this competitive pluralism" refers to the various claims made by his opponents).

a = Competition is vicious.

b = Every person is good at something.

c = Failure in one area is counterbalanced by success in another.

d = Each person finds a context in which he finds self-esteem, etc.

e = Success in some areas is accorded considerable social standing.

f = Success in others gives only limited acceptance.

    Others: b )
    ) ----> d ----> not a
    c )
    Kleinig: d, but
    e )
    ) [ ---> not c ] ----> a
    f )

This diagram suggests that Kleinig asserts "a", whereas in the passage given he may only reach as far as suggesting the conclusion "not c".

EXERCISE E

1. This is, I think, clearly meant to be a deductive argument.

2. This is the sort of argument I find difficult to classify. It is usually put forward as so obviously correct that people must think it is deductive; but it is in fact so obviously bad, both as a deductive or non-deductive argument, that one wonders what people are up to. The English word "educate" is not identical with any Latin word, so obviously nothing follows deductively from what a Latin word may have meant. Nor can I think of any plausible generalization about the way people use words which could be invoked to patch it up as a non-deductive argument (the word "pen" in "ball-point pen" comes from a Latin word meaning "feather" - so what?) And if our aim is to establish how we currently use a word, it seems incredibly perverse to start any kind of argument with what people did in a different language two thousand years ago.

3. Deductive. Like almost all mathematically based arguments, this one offers the deductive guarantee. It might be worth noting that it gives us a piece of knowledge about two people although we have no way of finding out which two people are in question.

4. Deductive, I think. The conclusion is stated in the first sentence, the premises in the second. There are also some unstated assumptions about the motivations and economic circumstances of the members addressed. Such assumptions are needed to link the facts that wines are at their cheapest when first available to buying them then being most economical for people, and the fact the choice is greatest to it being most satisfactory to buy then. There is a small complication because the claim is that it is almost certain that the wines will be at their least expensive; it doesn't follow from this that it will be most economical to buy them. But perhaps "satisfactory" can provide a way-out here: waiting for the bottom to fall out of the market might make it more economical but it might not be satisfactory.

5. Here we have a clear example of one type of non-deductive argument. The author gives evidence that points towards a certain explanation of the facts he mentions about an association between broken homes and delinquency. The evidence does not guarantee that explanation, as he indicates by using the word "suggests". Authors who claim that such evidence "proves" their case are misleading.

6. Deductive. There is an unstated assumption that monopoly and the accumulation of capital press men together. Adding this to the second sentence generates the main part of the conclusion stated in the first sentence. That conclusion also makes it plain what the author thinks of capital accumulation. Notice that evaluating the argument in the passage is not the same as evaluating the truth of the claims made. There is a difficulty in doing this other job because of the indefinite "favourable" and "ultimately".



URL http://www.uwichill.edu.bb/bnccde/epb/aa4-6.html

HTML prepared June 2000, last revised June 29th, 2000.

Return to list of publications.